encironmental ethics FROM THE PERSPECTIVE OF EARLY buddhism.pdf

(114 KB) Pobierz
660479750 UNPDF
A SUFFERING (BUT NOT IRREPARABLE)
NATURE: ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
FROM THE PERSPECTIVE OF EARLY
BUDDHISM
John J. Holder
Introduction: challenges to an early Buddhist environmentalism
In the last quarter century, concern for the environment has evolved from
the warnings sounded by a few to a globally shared awareness of environmental
problems. In the wake of this trend, philosophers and those studying or practicing
various religions have been seeking the ethical and spiritual resources that
are required to effectively respond to the various ecological crises. From the
beginning of this search for traditions that support environmental values,
Buddhism has stood out as especially promising. Numerous books and articles
have appeared that acclaim Buddhism’s strong support for environmental ethics. 1
For many of these authors, the Buddhist tradition offers an image of humanity
that is in a symbiotic or integrative relationship with the wider environment,
suggesting a less exploitative approach to nature than those found in other
religious traditions. Others consider the Buddhist ethical principle of ‘non-hurting’
(ahims ¯ ) and the naturalist aesthetics of Zen Buddhism as evidence that Buddhism
has an inherent environmental ethic.
In the past decade, however, Buddhist environmentalism has been called
into question by a number of scholars of early Buddhism. 2 For example, Ian Harris
and Lambert Schmithausen have argued that the central claims of those
promoting ‘Green Buddhism’ or ‘Eco-Buddhism’(as the blending of Buddhism and
environmental ethics has come to be called) do not hold up to careful scholarly
scrutiny, thus raising considerable skepticism about the prospects for Buddhist
environmentalism. 3 Most importantly, the skeptics point out that key claims of
Green Buddhism do not accurately reflect the doctrines of the early Buddhist
tradition as we have them recounted in the canonical sources such as the P ¯ li
Nik ¯ yas. 4 Let me briefly recount some of the major reasons that have been
advanced for this skepticism regarding the connection between environmental
ethics and early Buddhism.
Contemporary Buddhism, Vol. 8, No. 2, November 2007
ISSN 1463-9947 print/1476-7953 online/07/020113-130
q 2007 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/14639940701636091
660479750.001.png
114 JOHN J. HOLDER
First, Green Buddhists portray Buddhism as holding a very positive (some
might say ‘romantic’) view of the natural world. For proponents of Green
Buddhism, the natural world is something of obvious value that is worth caring for
and preserving. But, according to Schmithausen in his seminal essay ‘The Early
Buddhist Tradition and Ecological Ethics,’ early Buddhists placed no value on
nature, because the natural world was for them nothing more than a place
of ‘suffering, decay, death and impermanence’ (1997, 11). As Schmithausen
interprets early Buddhism, the natural world is fundamentally and irreparably
unsatisfactory (dukkha). For this reason, he asserts that ‘the ultimate analysis and
evaluation of existence in early Buddhism does not motivate efforts for preserving
nature, not to mention restoring it, nor efforts for transforming or subjugating it by
means of technology’ (ibid.; italics contained in original text). In opposition to
Green Buddhism, Schmithausen understands the goal of early Buddhism as
liberation from nature. No doubt, Schmithausen is right when he argues that early
Buddhism does not present a rosy picture of nature. But if he is correct that the
early Buddhist view of nature is fundamentally and irreparably negative, then it is
indeed difficult to see how early Buddhism could offer much in the way of
resources for environmental ethics.
Aside from this negative evaluation of nature, the skeptics have noticed that
early Buddhism lacks (or outright rejects) certain other key elements that define
contemporary environmental ethics. For example, a contemporary environmental
ethic is typically based on the idea that nature has an ‘intrinsic value’; that is,
nature is valued ‘for its own sake,’ rather than having merely instrumental value to
human beings. 5 But the early Buddhist tradition is unlikely to adopt the view that
the natural world has intrinsic value because the notion of intrinsic value depends
on a metaphysical position that gives independent, self-subsisting, existence to the
beings or things valued. But such a ‘substantialist’ metaphysics, as this position is
often called, is precisely the kind of metaphysics early Buddhism ardently rejects. 6
Furthermore, there is hardly any hint in the canonical sources that the early
Buddhists had a preference for ‘intact’ nature or unpopulated wilderness, despite
the enthusiastic accounts of Buddhist conservation by proponents of Green
Buddhism in the West. The early Buddhists may have retreated to the forests and
mountains for their meditative repose, but the early texts give no special place to
wilderness as such. 7 Quite the contrary, the texts seem to show that early
Buddhists favored human society over wilderness as evidenced by the Buddha’s
itinerary and his establishment of the monastic and lay communities (the fourfold
Sangha). Failing to find any evidence that, for early Buddhism, ‘intact nature and
natural diversity are accorded a positive value’ (Schmithausen 1997, 6) – factors
that some take as the sine qua non of an environmental ethic—the skeptics draw
the conclusion that early Buddhism cannot serve as a resource for ecological
ethics today.
Finally, it has been argued that trying to find solutions to our contemporary
environmental crisis in early Buddhism is highly anachronistic. Surely, the early
Buddhists cannot have much to say directly about contemporary environmental
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS FROM THE PERSPECTIVE OF EARLY BUDDHISM 115
problems, because most of these problems have emerged only in the past several
centuries. Deforestation, water pollution, air pollution, the extinction of countless
species of flora and fauna, ozone depletion, global warming (just to name a few)
are ecological problems that simply did not exist in the time of the Buddha (or, if
they did, they did not pose the significant threat that they do now). Indeed, it
would be strange to think that the early Buddhist tradition would show concern
for environmental problems that would not surface for another two millennia.
So, no matter how ‘green’ Buddhism was in its time, one cannot expect the
tradition to offer specific solutions to the environmental crises we now face. On
this matter, the skeptics are certainly right to caution against the anachronism in
presenting early Buddhism as a direct response to the environmental challenges
we face today.
These obstacles, taken together, seem to indicate a serious mismatch
between early Buddhism and contemporary environmental ethics. Indeed, for
these reasons, the prospects look dim for drawing on early Buddhism as a resource
for environmental ethics. So long as environmental ethics requires making ‘intact’
nature an ultimate value and early Buddhism is seen as world-denying escapism,
the conclusions of the skeptics appear unavoidable. But I do not think this is the
end of the story. Rather, I think the case against early Buddhist environmentalism
given above is flawed both in terms of methodology and doctrine. The typical
study of Buddhist environmentalism is methodologically flawed because both the
skeptics and the proponents of Buddhist environmentalism start with a
contemporary way of framing environmental ethics and try to match that
particular approach to environmental ethics with the ancient texts, doctrines, and
practices of early Buddhism. But this seems methodologically backward. It would
be like looking for an ancient Buddhist system of measurement by searching for a
modern unit of measurement (say, a ‘meter’) in the P¯ li texts—finding none, one
can imagine the skeptics announcing that the ancient Buddhists therefore had no
system of measurement at all. Rather than start with a modern conception of
environmental ethics as a criterion for whether early Buddhism has environmental
resources, one should start with early Buddhism itself and see whether, in accord
with its own doctrines, the tradition places a positive value on the natural world
and gives human beings guidance on how to act in relation to that natural world.
In terms of doctrine, I think it is wrong to see early Buddhism as a program for
escape from the natural world. Using the ancient sources, one can demonstrate
that the natural world has a positive value in early Buddhism.
In this essay, I will attempt to lay the groundwork for early Buddhist
environmental ethics by correcting these two mistakes and thus avoiding the
skeptical arguments adduced above. The first section of the essay is an exploration
of the relationship between human beings and the natural world posited in the
early Buddhist texts. I will argue that early Buddhism is best viewed as special type
of naturalism—an ‘emergentist’ naturalism. 8 Early Buddhism is a type of naturalism
because it explains all phenomena, including human beings, in terms of the causal
order of nature. For an early Buddhist environmental ethic, the important principle
116 JOHN J. HOLDER
that follows from this naturalism is the continuity of human beings with the natural
world.
But this human – nature continuity alone is insufficient as a basis for an
environmental ethic; to frame an environmental ethic, it must be coupled with the
ethical principles that derive from the Buddhist focus on dukkha (suffering,
anxiety, or unsatisfactoriness). According to the skeptics, dukkha is the greatest
obstacle to realizing early Buddhist environmental ethics because it implies an
utterly negative evaluation of nature. In the main body of the essay, I will argue
that the skeptics have gotten this wrong: nature has a profound value in early
Buddhism, as it is through natural means that one makes spiritual progress in early
Buddhism. Early Buddhism disparages only the type of existence that is fraught
with dukkha, not the natural world per se. Hence, early Buddhism is not a world-
denying philosophy that recommends a program for escape from the natural
world.
Dukkha is also the rationale for early Buddhist interest in protecting or
preserving the natural world. What makes the natural world an essential human
concern from a Buddhist point of view is the fact that the spiritual therapy for
confronting dukkha has a ‘de-centering’ effect that identifies human concern with
a concern for the suffering of all sentient beings (satt ¯, bh ¯ t ¯ ). Human – nature
continuity, which is the heart of Buddhist naturalism, thus has profound ethical
implications when, in the context of eliminating dukkha, it serves as the basis for
linking our own suffering and the suffering of other sentient beings.
In the last section of the essay, I will sketch in broad outline the general
direction I think an early Buddhist environmental ethics would take. What is clear is
that early Buddhist environmental ethics will have somewhat different priorities as
compared with contemporary (mainstream) environmental ethics, for it will derive
its moral principles directly (and indirectly) from the concern for the suffering of all
sentient beings and not from a concern for the ‘intrinsic value’ of an ‘intact’ nature.
The continuity of human beings with ‘nature’: emergentist
naturalism in early Buddhism
The conception of ‘nature’ (or the ‘natural world’) and its relationship to
human beings are the bases for any environmental ethic. Such matters figure
prominently in the skeptical arguments described above. Thus, the logical starting
point for a study of early Buddhist environmentalism is an analysis of the early
Buddhist conception of nature. Of course, the conception of ‘nature’ in the
modern scientific sense of the word is absent in the canonical texts. But there is a
broad conception of ‘nature’ or ‘natural’ in ancient Buddhism—covered by several
different words in P ¯ li 9 —that seems to be fairly close to our non-technical usage
today. Unfortunately, there are no discourses in the canonical literature that
expound a detailed theory of nature as such, at least not a theory with the kind of
generality one needs for articulating an environmental ethic. 10 But this is not an
insuperable difficulty. The Buddha gave accounts of many different types
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS FROM THE PERSPECTIVE OF EARLY BUDDHISM 117
of phenomena, so it only takes a short step of generalization to say that, for early
Buddhism, all phenomena fall within the category of the ‘natural.’ As the early
Buddhist texts explain, each phenomenon, everything that exists, is an
impermanent, conditioned, changing, process that is identical with the interplay
of causal factors. This is the all-important insight that served as the catalyst for the
Buddha’s enlightenment; namely, the doctrine of dependent arising
( paticcasamupp ¯da). According to the texts, the various things or phenomena
that make up the real world are dependently arisen (and, therefore, impermanent).
Of course, dependent arising as it appears in the texts is used mainly to explain
(and so control) the arising and cessation of dukkha in human experience. 11 The
pattern for dependent arising typically involves twelve (sometimes ten) nid ¯nas
(causal factors) with ‘this whole mass of dukkha’ as the terminus of the causal
chain. But causal principles are also used to explain many other phenomena in a
naturalistic way, including such things as plants, animals, fire, and wind.
Importantly, such is the limit of the ‘real world,’ as the Buddha defined it in the
famous Sabba Sutta (‘Discourse on the All’). 12 The ‘all’ refers to the objects
experienced through the six modes of sensory perception. This puts the ‘real’
squarely among the ‘natural’ existents rather than among the purportedly
transcendent, non-empirical, and unchanging realities claimed by other traditions
(notably, Brahmanism). As everything that exists is inextricably bound up in causal
connections, lacks a permanent essence, and is experienced by sensory modes of
perception, the horizon of reality for early Buddhism is the natural world. 13
The main thrust of early Buddhism is to explain human personhood as a
natural process emergent from other natural processes, rather than as a
permanent essence or soul (e.g., the Brahmanical ¯ tman). The early Buddhists
demonstrated the naturalness of the human person through the well-known
Buddhist doctrine of the ‘five aggregates’ or ‘bundles’ (khandh ¯). 14 Human beings
are composed of a body, feeling, perceptions, dispositions to action and
consciousness (nothing more nor less). All of these aggregates are dependently
arisen, causally emergent, and therefore natural processes. Human existence is
thus a function of psycho-existential factors that fall within a broadly construed
understanding of nature. The Buddha’s aim (and the great achievement,
according to Buddhists) is the explanation of dukkha as the result of identifiable
causal processes in the natural world, without any need for transcendental
realities or a supernatural self/soul ( ¯tman). Even human consciousness (vi ˜ ˜ ¯na),
the most obvious candidate for ‘supernatural’ or transcendent status, is explained
in naturalistic terms in the early discourses. In the Madhupi n dika Sutta, for
example, the six modes of human consciousness 15 arise dependent on a
combination of a particular sense faculty and a sensory object. Consciousness is
thus not a supernatural intruder in a physical world, but a natural process that
arises under certain complex conditions.
Two cautions about early Buddhist naturalism are in order. First, by referring
to early Buddhism as a form of naturalism, one must be quite careful not to think
of this as reductive or eliminative materialism. Reductive materialism explains all
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin